
The term ‘absolutism’ has both a moral and political connotation. In
terms of morality, ‘absolutism’ refers to at least two distinct
doctrines. Firstly, absolutism may refer to the claim that there exists a
universally valid moral system, which applies to everyone whether they
realize it or not. In this sense, absolutism is opposed to moral
relativism, which denies the existence of universally applicable moral
principles. Secondly, absolutism may refer to the claim that moral rules
or principles do not admit any exceptions. Immanuel Kant, for instance,
is an absolutist (in this sense) with respect to lying, because he held
that it is never permissible to lie. This variety of absolutist need
not maintain that all moral principles are absolute. Most contemporary
defenders of absolutism would not hold that lying is always
impermissible but may maintain this of (e.g., torture).
In terms of politics, ‘absolutism’ refers to a type of government in
which the ruler’s power is absolute, that is, not subject to any legal
constraints. The European monarchies, especially those of France, Spain,
and Russia, between the fifteenth and eighteenth centuries provide
perhaps the clearest examples of absolute rule, although forms of
absolutism have existed in most parts of the world. It was not until the
end of the eighteenth century that the prevalence of absolute rule in
Europe began to wane.
The word ‘absolutism’ does not have an entirely uniform meaning within
contemporary moral and political writings. This article outlines three
central uses of the term, which may serve as an introduction to the
topic.
Meta-ethical absolutism
“Absolutism” (or 'moral absolutism') refers, firstly, to a doctrine
about the nature of morality (meta-ethics), according to which there are
true or justifiable moral principles that have application to everyone,
or at least, all moral agents (excluding infants and the mentally
impaired for example). In other words, there are moral rules that apply
to all people, including those who do not acknowledge these principles
but live their lives in accordance with other, false, principles. Moral
absolutism in this sense is committed to the existence of universal
moral principles and for this reason is sometimes called universalism.
Moral absolutism in our first sense is opposed to moral relativism,
which denies that there are any moral principles that have universal
application. Rather, according to the relativist, moral principles apply
locally, that is, only to the groups of people who accept them. In
understanding the dispute between absolutism and relativism, it is
important to distinguish the question of ‘’universal applicability’’
from ‘’universal acceptance.’’ The relativist does not deny that is
possible (or even actual) that could be moral principles accepted by
everyone. What he denies is that these principles would also apply to
people who did not accept them. For example, suppose that as a result of
globalization, everyone in the world came to ‘’accept’’ (roughly) the
western moral code. (This is the moral code shaped by the influences of
Judaism and Christianity and held by most people living in Europe and
North America.) This would not imply the existence of any universal and
absolute moral code for it would not imply that this code applied to
others, such as future humans, who did not endorse this way of ethical
thinking. So the relativist would argue that a moral code could be
universally accepted, without being universally valid, and hence fail to
be absolute.
Moral absolutism presupposes objectivism—the doctrine that moral
principles are true, or justified, independently of anyone’s belief that
they are true or justified. This is because conventional moral codes
could not have any universal validity—for they are true only insofar as
they are believed to be true. Secondly, although moral absolutism is
committed to their being a universally valid set of moral principles, it
is not committed to saying that anyone currently knows this universal
moral code. So although a moral absolutist maintains that there is one
and only one proper moral code and that everyone ought to live by it, he
need not maintain that the code is known. However, it presumably must
be knowable, and once it is discovered all are morally obliged to live
by it. The reader is cautioned, however, that absolutists often write as
though they do know some of these principles, and at least one
contemporary writer characterizes absolutism in terms of ‘’knowledge’’
of an absolute moral code (see Cook 1999).
Many normative theories that would typically be discussed in an
introductory ethics class count as species of absolutism in our first
sense. For example, utilitarianism presents a theory of morality
according to which actions are right just in case they produce more
overall welfare than available alternatives. This is an absolute account
of morality, for it implies that there is, in all circumstances, one
correct answer as to what it is right to do. This applies to everyone,
even to those who did not know about or accept the utilitarian
principle. Similarly, Kant’s theory is also a species of absolutism for
it holds that moral right and wrong are all ultimately determined by a
basic principle of practical reason—the categorical imperative—and hence
applicable to all rational agents. Utilitarianism and Kantianism are
both forms of monism, the view that there is ultimately only one
absolute and basic moral principle. However, not all forms of absolutism
make this assumption. W.D. Ross’s theory, for example, endorses a
plurality of absolute moral principles, none of which are any more basic
than any other (see intuitionism). This is still an absolutist account
of morality in our first sense, that is the sense opposed to relativism,
because it claims universal applicability. W. D. Ross’s prima facie
duties prescribe, for example, that it is always prima facie wrong to
break a promise.
Moral absolutism
“Absolutism” (or 'moral absolutism) refers also to a particular type of
ethical theory, that is, a normative theory according to which some
actions (action-types) are absolutely forbidden. Absolutism in this
sense says, for example, that it is always wrong to kill, or always
wrong to lie, or always wrong to tortue another. It is important to
notice, however, that absolutism is not a theory of ‘’which’’ actions
are absolutely prohibited or required but only a theory that there
‘’are’’ some actions absolutely outlawed in this way. Absolutism upholds
only the formal requirement that some moral principles admit of no
exceptions—that there are some moral principles it is always wrong to
break. This implies that it is possible to be an absolutist about any
action-type whatsoever, although most absolutists argue for their
position by means of torture, killing of the innocent, and so on.
Moral absolutism in this second sense is often held as opposed to
consequentialism. Consequentialism is a theory according to which
actions are right just in case they promote overall value in comparison
with other alternatives. The upshot of this account is that no
particular action (or action-type) could be absolutely wrong. For
example, torturing a small child may produce more value (or less
disvalue) than the killing of an entire nation. Therefore, for a
consequentialist, torturing a small child in order to save a country is
permissible, if indeed not positively required. By contrast, moral
absolutism holds that some actions are absolutely wrong; they could
never be right no matter what consequences of failing to do them might
be. So, an absolutist would say that it is morally wrong to torture a
child in order to save an entire nation. Absolutism says that some
actions are wrong whatever the consequences. Or again, moral absolutism
about lying would say that the lying is always wrong, whatever the
consequences. Consequentialism is sometimes construed as one type of
absolutist moral theory: for instance, it is absolutely wrong not to act
in such a way that promotes overall value.
Which actions or types of action are traditionally regarded as
absolutely wrong? Historically, philosphers have been absolutists with
regarded to many types of actions such as lying, adutery, and sodomy.
However, in a contemporary setting, torture and executing the innocent
are two of the actions most commonly held to be absolute prohibitions.
And these are also the most plausible sort of cases. In fact, the United
Nations Convention against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or
Degrading Treatment or Punishment (1987) upholds an absolutism of this
form. "No exceptional circumstances whatsoever, whether a state of war
or a threat of war, internal political instability or any other public
emergency, may be invoked as a justification of torture" (Article 2).
This resolution says that no matter what the expected consequences of
torture may be—for example, preventing New York City from being bombed
by terrorists—torture is impermissible. It would be morally wrong to
torture a terrorist in order to find out where a bomb was being hidden,
even if the consequences of not doing so would be quite catastophic.
Given its emphasis on moral principles, and opposition to
consequentialism, it may seem unclear how absolutism differs from
deontology. The answer is that absolutism is a species of deontology.
Absolutism endorses two claims: (1) some actions are intrinsically right
or wrong; (2) the consequences of an action of this sort (e.g., lying)
can never override its intrinsic rightness or wrongness. By contrast, a
deontological ethical theory is committed to (1) but not to (2). All
absolutist theories are therefore deontological, but not all
deontological theories are absolutist.
Although deontological ethical theories are not necessarily absolutist,
some important deontologists have been. Kant’s infamous discussion of
the inquiring murderer suggests that he held that the deontological
constraint on lying is absolute. In his infamous essay, ‘On a Supposed
Right to Lie from Altruistic Motives’, Kant argues against the
permissibility of lying even to a man whom one knows to be in the
process of attempting a murder, going about looking for his victim. Kant
saus that ‘to be truthful (honest) in all deliberations … is a sacred
and absolutely commanding decree of reason, limited by no expediency.’
Kant is therefore an absolutist, for he would argue against lying under
any conditions. This is what makes him an absolutist: lying is forbidden
in every situation; it is never permissible to lie.
Similarly, an important contemporary deontologist, Charles Fried,
endorses absolutism in the following passage: “Ordinary moral
understanding, as well as many major traditions of Western moral theory,
recognize that there are some things which a moral man will not do, no
matter what…It is part of the idea that lying or murder are wrong, not
just bad, that these are things you must not do–no matter what. They are
not mere negatives that enter into a calculus to be outweighed by the
good you might do or the greater harm you might avoid. Thus the norms
which express deontological judgments–for example, Do not commit
murder–may be said to be absolute. They do not say: ‘Avoid lying, other
things being equal’, but ‘Do not lie, period’.” (Fried 1978)
Non-absolutist deontologists, such as W.D. Ross hold that one may in
exceptional circumstances break deontological constraints. Ross
distinguishes between prima facie duties and what he calls duties
proper. The concept of a prima facie duty is the concept of a duty,
which though it is a significant reason for not doing something, is not
absolute, but must be weighed up against other duties. A duty proper
refers to the action that must be done when all the prima facie duties
have been considered and weighed. To illustrate, Ross thinks that we
have duties to keep our promises, and duties of benevolence: these are,
then, prima facie duties. Insofar as these prima facie duties come into
conflict (and one cannot keep a promise and act with benevolence), one
must decide on the basis of contextual details, which of these duties is
most pressing. The action which is judged to be, all things considered,
the right thing to do, is the duty proper. Ross’s theory is an example
of a moderate deontology, that is, deontology without absolutism.
Political Absolutism
In it political sense, ‘absolutism’ is a theory of legislative
authority. It holds that the ruler, usually the king, has exclusive
legal authority, and consequently that the laws of state are nothing
other than expressions of his will (see voluntarism). Only divine and
natural laws limit the king’s power, which in it practical implication,
amounts to almost no limitation at all. In the terminology of Roman law,
the king is legibus solutus (‘unfettered legislator’). The European
monarchies, especially those of France, Spain, and Russia, between the
fifteenth and eighteenth centuries provide clear examples of absolutist
states, although many others, such as the dynasties of China and Japan,
also qualify. It was not until the end of the eighteenth century that
the prevalence of absolute rule in Europe began to wane.
In its most extreme form, absolutism interprets the power of the king,
and his right to rule, as derived directly from God. This is known as
the Divine Right of Kings (see Jacques-Bénigne Bossuet). On this view,
the monarch derives his authority as ruler directly from God, and not
from the will of his subjects, the nobility, or any other human
authority. According to a second form of absolutism, royal legislative
authority derives from a contract between ruler and subjects, in which
the people irreversibly transfer power to him. Once power has been
transferred in this way, the people are no longer entitled to replace
their ruler, although they might legitimately resist him in certain
extreme circumstances. Probably the most moderate form of absolutism
originates in the writings of the Jesuit jurist and theologian Francisco
Suárez, who argued that the authority of the ruler derives the people’s
delegating power to him. This differs from the second form of
absolutism since the transfer of power is not irreversible: the people
could legitimately, in some circumstances, reclaim the authority they
had delegated.